Congratulations to Michelle Bayefsky on winning the first Daniel Callahan Young Writer's Prize! Michelle will be receiving the prize award of $500 and a copy of Daniel Callahan's autobiography, In Search of the Good: A Life in Bioethics. Thank you to the finalist judges, Daniel Callahan, Michael Gusmano, and Laura Haupt (their bios can be found here).
Uterine Transplant: Where, If Anywhere, Should We Draw the Line?
By Michelle Bayefsky
By Michelle Bayefsky
In October 2014, researchers from the University of
Gothenburg in Sweden reported the first case of a live birth following a uterine
transplant. The uterus was transplanted from a postmenopausal woman into a 36
year-old woman born without a uterus. At nearly 32 weeks of pregnancy, she gave
birth to a male child with normal birth weight for gestational age and
excellent APGAR scores.[1]
The birth of this child represents a tremendous breakthrough
in the treatment of infertility. There are many causes of female infertility, including
damaged fallopian tubes, premature menopause and endometrial (uterine tissue)
abnormalities. Corresponding treatments include in vitro fertilization, use of donor eggs, and use of a gestational
surrogate. Uterine transplantation could obviate the need for gestational
surrogates for patients with uterine infertility, allowing these mothers-to-be
to carry their own pregnancies and potentially precipitating a decline of the
controversial practice of surrogacy.
But why stop there? If uterine transplantation is a
treatment for absolute uterine infertility, trans-women also have this
condition, and so do all men. In this essay, I will explore whether and where to
draw the line for those who should be eligible for a uterine transplant.
It is not yet possible for individuals with XY sex
chromosomes to gestate a child. However, the desire for transgender women to
carry a pregnancy is present,[2]
and at least one bioethicist, Timothy Murphy, has begun to think about the
prospect of uterine transplants into trans-women.[3]
Murphy correctly focuses on state funding, since the hands-off regulatory
attitude towards reproductive medicine in the United States[4]
makes it unlikely that transgender uterine transplants would be banned
outright. The debate about the appropriateness of transgender uterine
transplants will therefore center on the need to prioritize limited healthcare resources.[5]
There are two central questions at stake. First, is there
such a thing as a right to a uterine
transplant? Second, is there a reason to distinguish between cis-women,
trans-women, and men with regards to their claims to a uterine transplant,
whether or not rights are at stake? If so, the state could be justified in
prioritizing the needs of cis-women over trans-women over men who desire to
gestate a child.
Uteruses are a scarce resource, and the state cannot ensure
uteruses to all those who might lack and strongly desire them. It is therefore difficult
to claim that people have a right to
a uterine transplant, though they may have a right to fair access to an
established supply of uteruses, should one come to exist. The scarcity issue is
compounded by the fact that uteruses, like other organs, exist within other
people’s bodies. Unless a sufficient number of uteruses are supplied via donation,
claiming a right to a uterine transplant would be claiming a right to someone
else’s body part. One could conceive of body parts as public goods, but such a
view would violate our closely held beliefs about bodily autonomy. Since the
state cannot forcibly redistribute organs, the right to a uterus can only be a
right in an abstract sense. Nevertheless, the relative strength of claims to
this abstract right can be used to determine what constitutes fair access to
the limited supply of uteruses. Who, if anyone, should be prioritized?
Answering this question requires that we carefully examine our
notions of infertility and instincts about childbearing. Intuitively, we might
think there are reasons to differentiate among cis-women, trans-women, and men based
on physical features and what it means to be “infertile.” For instance, it may be
tempting to argue that cis-women without uteruses are infertile because they
lack the typical reproductive organs of an XX-woman, while trans-women and men
are fertile because they can still use sperm to ‘father’ children in the
classic XY manner. However, all three categories are fertile in terms of their
gametic capacity to reproduce but infertile with regards to the capacity to
gestate.
One might also attempt to argue that women, whether cis or
trans, have a stronger claim to the experience of carrying a child because it
is typically a woman’s experience and part of being female. However, many women
choose not to have children and are not lesser women because of it.
Furthermore, arguments about childbearing based on assumptions about what it
means to be a woman risk unjustly imposing societal norms and expectations on
women, both cis and trans.
It may seem that distinctions among the three groups most
plausibly rely on assertions relating to the prospective happiness of the
transplant recipient. It is possible that cis-women have greater childbearing expectations,
and would be most anguished by the inability to carry a pregnancy and should thus
be given highest priority. Similarly, trans-women, who identify as the sex that
typically bears children, may be more anguished than a self-identifying man. It
is easy to imagine, though, a trans-woman who has always longed to gestate a
child, or even a man with a very strong desire to carry a child, who would
suffer deeply if they could not obtain a uterine transplant – even more than
some cis-women without functional uteruses. Thus psychological impact could not
reliably be used to distinguish among the three groups.
Ultimately, a priori distinctions could most reasonably be
made on the basis of differential resource expenditure. If uterine transplantation
is significantly easier, more successful or less expensive in a cis-woman, or a
trans-woman who has undergone hormone therapy, this justifies prioritizing these
groups the same way recipients are prioritized in the donation of other organs.[6]
Realistically, given the general lack of coverage for
fertility services in the United States,[7]
it is unlikely that either cis or trans-gender uterine transplants will be funded
in the near future.
However, if uterine transplants do receive public funding
and transplants into XY women and men are equally successful and no more
economically burdensome than transplants into XX women, trans-women, as well as
men with a profound desire to gestate, should be equally eligible to receive a
uterine transplant.
Michelle Bayefsky is a first-year pre-doctoral
fellow in the Department of Bioethics for the National Institutes of Health.
She graduated from Yale University in 2014 with a B.A. in Ethics, Politics and
Economics. She worked as a research assistant for two consecutive directors of
the Yale Interdisciplinary Center for Bioethics. She also founded and served as
Editor-in-Chief of the Yale Bioethics Journal. Michelle currently investigates
ethical challenges posed by innovations in genetic technology, issues related
to the regulation of genetic testing, and questions that arise at the
intersection of genetics and reproductive medicine.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
[1] Brännström, M., L. Johannesson, et al. (2014). "Livebirth after uterus transplantation." The Lancet.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
[1] Brännström, M., L. Johannesson, et al. (2014). "Livebirth after uterus transplantation." The Lancet.
[2] Mott,
Stephanie. "Trans-Uterus." The Huffington Post. TheHuffingtonPost.com,
21 Jan. 2014. Web. 14 Nov. 2014.
[3] Murphy,
Timothy. "The Ethics of Helping Transgender Men and Women Have
Children." Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 53.1 (2010): 46-60.
[4] Leigh, Suzanne.
"Reproductive 'tourism'" USA Today - Health and Behavior.
USATODAY.com, 02 May 2005. Web. 19 Sept. 2014; Williams, Benjamin.
"Screening for Children: Choice and Chance in the “Wild West” of
Reproductive Medicine." George Washington Law Review 79.4 (2011):
1305-342.
[5] Murphy,
Timothy. "Uterus Transplants for Transgender Women?" Weblog post.
Ethics and Choices about Children. Timothyfmurphy.blogspot.com, 27 Apr. 2014.
Web. 14 Nov. 2014.
[6] The use of
cost-effectiveness arguments in prioritizing organ transplantation is itself
controversial (see, for example, Dan Brock, “Ethical Issues in the Use of Cost
Effectiveness Analysis for the Prioritisation of Health Care Resources”), but I
cannot explore this issue here.
[7] "State
Laws Related To Insurance Coverage for Infertility Treatment." Insurance
Coverage for Infertility Laws. National Conference of State Legislatures,
Jun. 2014. Web. 12 Nov. 2014.