This piece begins a bi-weekly column devoted to reproductive issues.
By Naomi Scheinerman
Those thinking of having children or who find themselves accidentally
pregnant ask many important questions: Am I ready to be a parent? Am I
financially able to support myself and
a child? Do I have the time and energy? Though these questions are undoubtedly
crucial, they are incomplete. One should also ask: would the child want its life?
The politics of childbirth in the United States are replete with
problems: states passing draconian anti-abortion legislation, a hospital keeping a brain-dead pregnant woman on a ventilator because of her nonviable fetus, employers denying paid maternal or parental leave, and religious groups denying their employees the freedom to choose contraception. Our
system is also hypocritical: we stigmatize teen or single mother pregnancy while
fighting contraceptive access; we fight expanding needed health care to poor and impoverished children while mistreating obese pregnant women; and we harass
abortion clinics while pushing for abstinence-only education in schools.
When deciding whether to conceive, it is crucial to ask whether the
fetus’s future life is optimal, rather than whether our life is optimal with a
child in it. This does not mean that we are obligated to have a child when we can provide an optimal life, nor does it
mean that we must define optimal according to one rigid standard. Rather, it
means that we should reformulate “Are we ready to have a child?” as “Is the
child going to be happy with this life?” I do not posit that either a woman’s
right to reproduce or her interests and welfare should ever be compromised
because of our concern for the fetus. Indeed, we too often disproportionately
value the welfare of the fetus over the mother, resulting at times in tragic death. Though a fetus deserves our respect and women do have certain
obligations to maintain a reasonable level of health for the fetus’s welfare,
fetuses do not carry nearly the same moral standing as the mothers. Further, there
is a connection between the above questions: if a woman, or man, is neither
emotionally nor financially ready to have a child, then that child most likely
will not want the life offered at that point in time.
There are certain philosophical objections one could raise with my position.
First, the classic nonidentity problem: it is wrong to say that being born in a
diminished state of existence has harmed a child because the child could not
have existed otherwise, For example, a woman who gives birth to a child she
knows has a debilitating genetic disorder has not harmed the child because that
unique child could not have lived any other way. The problem with the
nonidentity objection is that it assumes it is always good to create life, no
matter what quality that life has. Further, it does not make sense to talk
about eggs, sperm, embryos, and early stage fetuses as though they have
consciousness and autonomous rights over their future selves.
A second possible objection is that precisely because the fetus does
not have autonomous rights over its future self, we cannot project its
preferences regarding life into the future. I agree with this statement,
however it does not do enough to dispute my claim. I am arguing for
reframing procreative decision-making to place the child as the most
important recipient of its life, rather than the parents. This is not because
the fetus has a right to that life, but rather because the child who is born
has a right to the best life possible.
Many posit that having a child is a selfish act. However, this does not concern me: if it is selfish and the child is happy, what’s the problem? And if it’s not selfish, and the child is happy, again what’s the problem? There are many decisions prospective parents or parents thinking of having another child must consider. Reframing the question in terms of the perspective of the newborn child and the development of that individual would yield a far more desirous outcome for all involved.
Naomi
Scheinerman is a Research Assistant at The Hastings Center. She graduated Phi Beta Kappa, with high
honors and in distinction from the University of Michigan in Ann Arbor, where
she received bachelor’s degrees in philosophy, political science, and Hebrew
and Jewish Cultural Studies.
No comments:
Post a Comment